Category Archives: 12. global legality

a. summary

GLOBAL LEGALITY
& POLLUTION AS A COMMON 

Is garbage part of the commons? Pollution has more rights than us as it doesn’t need a passport to cross national boundaries. Hence the question if pollution should not also be a common? This chapter zooms in on the global politics and the stature of the commons within international law. How can we govern the commons globally? Who owns the earth? Who owns the air? Who owns the climate? Who owns outer space? A changing nature of law is redefining how forests, trees and even rivers (e.g. the Whangui river in New Zealand) attain legal status, but who will share these laws and does it take into account indigenous stewardship questioning legal ownership? Or can corporations like Bayer-Monsanto be held accountable for ecocide by the International Court of the Hague (e.g. 2017 Monsanto Tribunal for ecocide)?

If we are to understand the law of the commons, we must start by expanding our notion of law itself. Law is not just formal, written and institutional; it is also informal, oral and social. The law of the commons represents something of a threat to formal law because its substance and legitimacy derive from the always-shifting social practices of the community. “Commoning” is often experienced as more responsive and morally legitimate than state law, particularly when the state itself is rigid, corrupt, incompetent or captive to corporate influence.

In a brilliant essay, “The Life of the Law Online,” legal scholar David R. Johnson likens law to a biological organism. He sees law as more closely resembling life than a machine; in this sense, it has a life and history of its own. “Law is a story we tell each other about justice and shared social values,” writes Johnson. “We have to retell this story every day — it replicates and persists only insofar as we do that.” (David Bollier: Think like a Commoner, 2014: 85)

Custom is therefore a vital element of the law of the commons. It functions as a cultural code that provides a unifying social ethic to a community. It is a shared narrative that links the community to earlier generations, and to a repository of wisdom about local resources and how best to manage them. As property scholar Carol Rose puts it, custom is “a medium through which a seemingly ‘unorganized’ public may organize itself and act, and in a sense even ‘speak’ with the force of law.”

This corresponds to David Johnson’s claim that law amounts to a “self-referential, organizational identity” that belongs to the people who make it. “If law has a life of its own,” he writes, “and in some sense causes its own form of order and persistence, we should be studying its biography rather than pretending that we can design and repair its mechanisms from the outside.” In other words, we must understand the subjective, socially internal dynamics of commons and recognize that this is where law originates.

When law is seen in this perspective — not just as a series of formal constitutions and statutes but as a self-organized system that a community creates to manage itself and its resources in orderly fair ways — it is easy to see that the commons itself is a living embodiment of law. It amounts to an evolving social

contract. Individuals come together to negotiate the rules and norms that will govern their community. They specify how members may access and use shared resources. They set about making rules for managing land, water, fish and wild game, and for monitoring usage and punishing vandals and free riders. In this broader sense, the law of the commons extends into the mists of time and precedes formal written law by many millennia.

From the outside, the law of the commons as embodied in an indigenous culture may seem static and slow moving, even frozen. But in truth, “commons law” constantly adapts to changes, often in small incremental ways. It is especially mindful of local realities: its signature strength. The tensions arise when formal, written law is not roughly congruent with such “commons law” and does not leave space for commoning. Is formal state law too strict and rigid — or is it open to change through peaceable politics and due process? Does it so insist upon market relationships and norms such that real citizenship is not possible?

Throughout history, state law has occasionally recognized the “vernacular law” of commoners — or at least, larger public needs — by formalizing such principles within the legal apparatus of the state. One of the earliest such instances of this occurred in the Roman Empire, which recognized explicit categories of law for property, including common property. In 535 AD, Emperor Justinian gave the first legal recognition of the commons when he enshrined res communes in his Institutes of Justinian body of law. “By the law of nature these things are common to mankind — the air, running water, the sea and consequently the shores of the sea. . . . Also all rivers and ports are public, so that the right of fishing in a port and in rivers is common to all. And by the law of nations the use of the shore is also public, and in the same manner, the sea itself. The right of fishing in the sea from the shore belongs to all men.” (emphasis in original). (David Bollier: Think like a Commoner, 2014: 86-87)

This legal principle — that neither the State, commerce nor citizens could make proprietary claims on resources that belong to everyone — has survived in what is known in American law as the “public trust doctrine.” This doctrine formalizes the idea that the State has an affirmative duty to protect natural resources for present and future generations; it cannot sell or give away land, water or wildlife to any private party. The public trust doctrine has traditionally been applied to rivers, oceans and the coastal shoreline, and is invoked to protect the right of the unorganized public to use those waters for fishing, navigation and recreation.

It is significant that res communes is a separate category from res publicae, another legal category that describes public things that belong to the state. Res communes is not simply “state-owned” property, but a class of property that lies beyond the power of the state. (David Bollier: Think like a Commoner, 2014: 88)

 

b. Slavoj Zizek: Nature Does Not Exist

SLAVOJ ZIZEK: NATURE DOES NOT EXIST

VPRO – Tegenlicht, The Netherlands
2010, 3 min 58 sec

Controversial Slovenian philosopher, Slavoj Žižek, talks about the ongoing ecological crisis and concludes that Nature doesn’t exist.

Not humanity’s impotence but rather omnipotence is terrifying, since we can’t grasp the impact of the power of that omnipotence. This takes us to the treshold of a new era: the antropocene, in which humanity literally becomes a geological factor. For instance, certain human activity can cause earth quakes.Conclusion? Maybe, paradoxically, nature does not exist.The image of nature that we spontaneously accept, that it’s balanced, harmonised, and gets destroyed by excessive human angecy, that nature does not exist.

c. A King in New York

A KID EXPLAINING TO AN OLD MAN WHAT AN ANARCHIST IS AND WHY GOVERNMENT EQUALS VIOLENCE

A King in New York, USA
1957, 3 min 58 sec

Rupert, a young editor of a school magazine, gets interrupted while reading Kalr Marx’ work to be introduced to ‘Your Majesty’. He seizes the opportunity to explain passionately why he dislikes all forms of government,since its power is antagonizing the people.

According to Rupert, politics are rules imposed upon the people.The importance of a passport and the restriction of freedom when lack of it is infuriating to the young man.

Since he believes there is no chance to compete with monoplized businesses he concludes that monopoly is the menace of free enterprise.Hence, the monopoly of power is a menace to freedom.

d. Monsanto Tribunal

MONSANTO TRIBUNAL

Ruptly tv, The Hague
2017, 1 min 29 sec

Judges of the Monsanto Tribunal delivered their legal opinion regarding the activity of the agro-chemicals giant Monsanto at The Hague, Tuesday, arguing that the company has violated basic human rights to food and health.

Having examined testimonies of witnesses, the judges concluded that “there has been an infringement on the right to food,” including by “denying peasants access to the seeds they need” and that the tribunal “considers that Monsanto’s conduct has offended the right to health.”

The tribunal comes after a growing number of lawsuits have been filed against Monsanto over allegations that one of the much maligned corporation’s herbicides is a cause of malformations in babies and cancer in agricultural workers.

e. further research

FURTHER READING & RESEARCH

Vandana Shiva, Protect or Plunder?  Understanding Intellectual Property Rights (2001)

Michael F. Brown, Who Owns Native Culture? (2004)

Crottorf Castle report of international retreat on the commons

http://www.onthecommons.org/content.php?id=2489

http://www.onthecommons.org/content.php?id=2490

http://www.onthecommons.org/content.php?id=2491

Alain Lipietz’ essay on the commons  / on political ecology

http://www.onthecommons.org/content.php?id=2590

http://www.onthecommons.org/alain-lipietzs-wisdom#sthash.aw723lsg.dpbs

http://lipietz.net/ALPC/Lectures/LEC_290.pdf

Barcelona Charter for Innovation, Creativity and Access to Knowledge

https://fcforum.net/en/charter/

http://www.fcforum.net

World Social Forum, Reclaim the Commons http://bienscommuns.org/signature/appel/?a=appel&lang=en

Commons Manifesto:  Strengthen the Commons.  Now!   

http://commonsblog.wordpress.com/2009/12/17/commons-manifesto-strenghten-the-commons-now

David Martin:  Global Innovation Trust and heritable trusts for indigenous peoples

http://www.invertedalchemy.blogspot.com/

http://www.globalinnovationcommons.org/

http://www.pitic.org.au/index.php?option=com_content&task=view&id=458&Itemid=118

Maria Mies & Veronika Benholdt-Thomsen:

Defending, Reclaiming and Reinventing the Commons
http://sduk.us/silvia_george_david/mies_benholdt_defending_reinventing.pdf